A DEEP CRITIQUE OF UPB!

  • 6 months ago
"Let me use Stefan's answer to the question "Can we be certain about the future?" – which you can find in his September 27 Wednesday Night Livestream at 1:23:07 – as an opportunity to publish a short essay I have written after reading The Art of the Argument...."

Join the PREMIUM philosophy community on the web for free!

Get my new series on the Truth About the French Revolution, access to the audiobook for my new book 'Peaceful Parenting,' StefBOT-AI, private livestreams, premium call in shows, the 22 Part History of Philosophers series and more!

See you soon!

https://freedomain.locals.com/support/promo/UPB2022
Transcript
00:00 I'll write you well. Good morning everybody, hope you're doing well. So somebody wrote me
00:04 an essay some time ago, I'm sorry it took me so long to get to it, but he wrote me an essay which
00:12 is wonderful, a great set of questions, I really appreciate the pushback and the critiques,
00:15 so let's see if we can't sharpen this diamond to a slightly brighter hue. He says "The Argument and
00:22 Consequentialism" and he said "Let me use Stefan's answer to the question 'Can we be certain about
00:26 the future?' which you can find in his September 27th, 2023 Wednesday night live stream at 1 hour
00:33 23 minutes and 7 seconds as an opportunity to publish a short essay I've written after reading
00:38 The Art of the Argument. Motivation. This is not a rebuttal to The Art of the Argument, I would have
00:45 to write a book to do that which I have no intention of doing so, I have no problem with 99%
00:48 of what Stefan is saying in the book. This is a criticism of Stefan's view of consequentialism
00:54 and determinism. As an empiricist he focuses on the evidence and I don't want to criticize
00:59 empiricism. In my opinion empiricism is crucial to rationality and true freedom and Stefan is saving
01:07 it where it needs to be saved in our everyday lives, but empiricism is only one side of the coin
01:12 and that's what this is about." And he makes a note that quotes in italics are from the book
01:17 The Art of the Argument, Western Civilizations Last Stand, artoftheargument.com, you should
01:22 totally check it out. What is consequentialism? So he quotes from the satanic temple of wikipedia
01:29 and says "in ethical philosophy consequentialism is a class of normative teleological ethical
01:37 theories that holds that the consequences of one's conduct are the ultimate basis for judgment about
01:44 the rightness or wrongness of that conduct. Thus from a consequentialist standpoint a morally
01:51 right act or omission from acting is one that will produce a good outcome." All right so as a little
02:01 bit of... so normative simply means prescribing a norm or a standard which are pretty basic to
02:08 ethics. Teleological refers to something that has a design or a purpose particularly in nature so
02:17 that's consequentialism right? "Freedom and consequentialism" he writes and this is a quote
02:22 from me from page 36 of The Art of the Argument. "The argument occurs every time you try to convince
02:27 someone else of your position or preference without using threats or force." And then he
02:32 writes "from a consequentialist standpoint an argument occurs when the consequentialist tries
02:36 to convince someone of what he believes a good or bad outcome will be. Thus a consequentialist
02:43 argument is a value argument with its alleged value living somewhere in the future. The value
02:48 is not true yet but it could become true." All right I'm down with that as a definition not
02:55 necessarily as a final argument. And then he quotes from my book page 7 "a truth argument
03:01 cares nothing for consequences a value argument cannot be defined by consequences but cannot be
03:05 indifferent either." And then he writes "the main motivation of consequentialism is to be not
03:11 indifferent of the future." So when facing a consequentialist statement we are facing a person
03:17 who wants to affect our free will choices in order to achieve a behavioral change for the
03:22 sake of a different outcome in the future. This has everything to do with freedom so we must be
03:26 very careful. All right so it started off well with some great setup and all of that but here's
03:34 the problem. The main motivation of consequentialism is to be not indifferent of the future. Now
03:41 that's a kind of foggy goop that seems to mean something but really doesn't.
03:48 So with philosophy we should be little concerned with motivations. Why? Because motivations
03:57 are a subjective claim. If somebody says "I'm motivated by x" how on earth are you supposed
04:05 to disprove that statement? How on earth are you supposed to disprove that statement? And so
04:13 philosophy cannot take as is any of its moral axioms the question of motivation because moral
04:21 axioms have to be founded in facts, truth, empiricism, syllogisms. They have to be unassailable
04:27 and if you're trying to build something that's unassailable then you can't have a subjective
04:34 claim as the foundation for anything to do with that. Right? We, I mean you've heard this all the
04:39 time in the call-in shows with regards to parents who misbehaved in the past or did bad things in
04:44 the past. What do they say? We did the best we could with the knowledge we had. There's no way
04:50 to prove any of that and when people make subjective claims I think that's fine. If somebody says
04:58 "I prefer the color red over the color blue" I think, I mean what am I going to do? Argue with
05:03 them? They're making a subjective claim. But there's no place in philosophy. There's no place
05:09 in philosophy. Can you imagine judging the value of a scientific theory by the stated motivations
05:16 of the scientist? It would make no sense. Right? Can you imagine judging the validity of a
05:25 mathematical solution by the color preference of the mathematician? Would make no sense at all.
05:32 So when people say, he writes, "the main motivation of consequentialism is to be not
05:39 indifferent of the future" I mean I won't say he's already lost me because you know it's worth
05:45 examining these things in more detail but why on earth would I care from a philosophical standpoint
05:51 about the imaginary motivations of people who claim to be fans or advocates of consequentialism?
05:59 So I don't really get this and you know just when you are writing to me or to anyone you want to be
06:07 taken seriously the art of the argument is organized very sort of specifically and carefully.
06:12 There are syllogisms, there's inductive and deductive reasoning definitions, there's a
06:16 passionate plea for why reason and evidence is so important because the only alternative is threats
06:21 and force. So I put the book very carefully together and put a lot of thought into how to
06:27 make the case. So when somebody says to me the main motivation of consequentialism is to be not
06:33 indifferent of the future he's bringing in something called motivation which he doesn't know.
06:38 He can't possibly know and so when somebody starts off their truth claim by something they can't
06:44 possibly know and even if they know it I can't verify it and if I can't verify it it's not part
06:52 of a debate. If you say well I dreamt of an elephant last night there's no possible way for
06:58 me to verify that. I may believe you, I may not believe you but it doesn't matter. I mean can
07:03 you imagine if someone has a will like your grandfather has a will that leaves everything
07:08 to your brother and then you're with your grandfather when he dies and you say my
07:14 grandfather whispered to me that everything should come to me and not go to my brother
07:19 would any court in the world accept that? Well no because there's no verification, there's no
07:26 notarization, there's no test for sound minds, there's simply your word against the stated
07:32 notarized legal will of the document. So that which cannot be independently verified has no
07:42 place in moral philosophy. That which cannot be independently verified right so when I make a
07:48 case about UPB, make the case for UPB you can independently verify that. You can run that through
07:53 logic, reason, evidence and so on and you can determine whether what my claims are are true.
07:59 So when somebody says the main motivation of consequentialism is to be not indifferent of
08:04 the future he's saying that he knows the motivations of all people who are pro-consequentialism. He
08:12 knows their motivations or is he saying that the philosophy itself has a kind of motivation
08:18 but an argument doesn't have motivation. Human beings have motivations. You see the argument,
08:24 the argument doesn't see you right. So it's all quite confusing in terms of what he's saying and
08:31 when you are reading something that's particularly rigorous as in the art of the argument,
08:38 took great care in putting all that together. When you read something that's particularly rigorous
08:43 and then you start with subjective assertions of the motivations of all those who are advocates
08:50 for consequentialism, I don't really know what to say about that other than you're really missing
08:57 the boat. Right you're really missing the boat. I mean I kind of hate that phrase you've lost the
09:02 plot because it doesn't really mean anything but it's not anything substantial. And then he and
09:08 the other thing too is well of course philosophy is not indifferent to the future and I say that
09:12 right there. I say a value argument cannot be defined by consequences but it cannot be
09:16 indifferent either. So what I mean by that is if you're saying it's morally good to mass murder
09:25 then we wouldn't want you to put your theory into practice. Right we wouldn't want you to
09:32 test your theory. This is of course the great question that Dostoevsky poses in Crime and
09:37 Punishment. Raskolnikov has a theory about property. He has a theory about the legitimate
09:43 use of violence which he describes in great detail in an essay he writes before he commits his crime.
09:47 So value arguments can't be indifferent to consequences. We won't try a bunch of mass
09:54 murdering to see if it works but it's not defined by its consequences. So to be not indifferent of
10:02 the future well of course philosophy is about changing our behavior for the better. Now the
10:08 change of that behavior for the better will always exist in the future because we cannot change the
10:15 behavior that we have exhibited in the past. I mean if you go to a nutritionist and you're 300
10:20 pounds the nutritionist is doing what? Well the nutritionist is making the case that you should
10:27 change your eating habits in order to lose weight and be healthier in the future. I mean there's no
10:32 magic wand. I'm sure it would be pretty pretty popular if there were but there's no magic wand
10:36 that a nutritionist can wave to have you not eat excess calories for the past 10 years and end up
10:41 with 300 pounds. That doesn't exist. So to say that a nutritionist is indifferent to the future
10:49 is obviously false. Any doctor, any physical trainer and a moral philosopher are all making
10:55 cases and arguments for you to change your habits or solve a problem in order to improve something
11:01 in the future or at least not have it get worse. So all human mental disciplines that aim to change
11:08 behavior are designed for the future. I mean we even study history which is behavior that can't
11:15 be changed in order to make better decisions in the future. All human thought bends towards the
11:19 future because all human thought is designed to change behavior for the better and that change
11:24 of behavior for the better only exists in the future. So if you're saying the main motivation
11:30 of consequentialism is to be not indifferent of the future you would have to say why consequentialism
11:36 is the only mental discipline or a discipline wherein the major focus as opposed to other
11:42 disciplines is interest in the future. Sorry that was badly worded. Let me try that again.
11:48 Let's say I say the main characteristic of consequentialism is that it uses language.
11:55 If I say the main characteristic of consequentialism is that it uses language,
12:00 I mean of course you would reply and rightly so, "well yes I accept that consequentialism uses
12:06 language but if you're going to say that the main characteristic, the primary characteristic of
12:11 consequentialism is that it uses language you would then have to explain how it ranks with
12:17 all the other human disciplines that use language. If you say the main motivation of consequentialism
12:25 is to change behavior in the future, well again you'd have to say why it would be differentiated
12:32 from all other mental, scientific, medical or other disciplines that aim to change behavior
12:38 in the future. I mean every ad on TV or online aims to change your behavior in the future.
12:46 Every diet or nutrition book aims to change your behavior in the future. Every politician is trying
12:52 to get you to change your behavior in the future or at least maintain your behavior if you're
12:56 already going to vote for him, to have you not change to not voting for him. So everyone's
13:01 trying to convince you to change your behavior in the future. What differentiates consequentialism
13:07 from all other human disciplines that aim to change your behavior in the future? So yeah.
13:12 So he says so when facing a consequentialist statement we are facing a person who wants to
13:16 affect our free will choices in order to achieve a behavioral change for the sake of a different
13:21 outcome in the future. Right. So a person who wants to affect our free will choices in order
13:26 to achieve a behavioral change for the sake of a different outcome in the future, that's everyone.
13:29 And then he says this is everything to do with freedom so you must be very careful.
13:34 Now I do have a certain amount of impatience with the caution people. You've got to be so careful.
13:42 It's like yeah. I mean I'm afraid that sort of modern discourse has become such a low-rent
13:48 WWF oiled bicep brawl fest that all the people who are saying you've got to be super careful
13:53 probably aren't going to be doing much helpful stuff in that domain. Okay so then he says
13:59 consequentialism and threats. Now sorry what I would say, and just go back to the last paragraph,
14:04 what I would say is that consequentialism aims to change your behavior by claiming certain,
14:12 not to change your moral behavior or to make a moral argument by making certain claims about
14:17 the outcome of choice. To make certain claims about the outcome of choice. But he's not making
14:24 that. He's just saying consequentialism wants to change our behavior in the future but that's too
14:29 wide a brush right. Almost every human discipline, almost every human communication wants to change
14:34 behavior in the future. I mean when you go to a coffee shop and you order a coffee you're trying
14:38 to change the barista's behavior in the future to make you a coffee. Oh anyway consequentialism and
14:44 threats. He says a threat is a communication of intent to inflict harm or loss on another person
14:50 but harm or loss, in other words bad consequences, are not always the result of a threat.
14:55 The question is why would someone want to talk about or even promise bad consequences? Okay
15:03 sure. There's a large circle called bad consequences, being hit by a bus, getting
15:11 cancer or whatever right, hit by a meteor and or getting fired or something unjustly right. So
15:17 yes there's a big circle called bad outcomes and there's a smaller circle which says harm or loss
15:26 threat. Right small small right. So one is just bad stuff happens, bad outcomes. The bad outcomes
15:31 could be you smoke for a long time and then you get lung cancer. So you've got a big big circle
15:36 called bad outcomes. Now inside that there's a much smaller circle called threats right. So yes
15:41 a threat is always a threat of a bad outcome but not all bad outcomes in life are part of a threat
15:46 and that's you know that's so blindingly obvious that I don't even know what to say.
15:52 Right if somebody says you know a lot of people have bad outcomes based on their choices
16:00 but some people have bad outcomes not based on their choices. It's just bad luck and and is this
16:06 a profound statement? Is this a profound moral statement? It's not. Some people get into car
16:14 accidents because they're driving badly but did you know Steph that a lot of people get into car
16:20 accidents when they're not driving badly. It's bad road conditions, it's the error or even bad
16:26 driving of another driver, it's a mechanical failure when they've kept their car maintained
16:30 and it's just one of these statements that's it's it's not the end of the world when something is
16:36 blindingly obvious and adds nothing to anybody over about two and a half years of age right.
16:41 I mean if I said to my daughter when she was two and a half I said you know there's candy in the
16:47 house but did you know there's also candy in the world and that the candy in the house is just a
16:50 small part of the candy in the world she'd say well duh I know we see it every time. So if it's
16:55 blindingly obvious to a two and a half year old but it's intoned with great solemnity to me I have
17:00 a certain amount of hmm why you now it's one thing if somebody says look I know that this is
17:06 blindingly obvious I understand that this is plenty obvious I have a reason for telling you
17:10 I have a reason for telling you and just be be patient right be patient and I'm sorry to say
17:17 something so blindingly obvious but I have a reason or you know whatever whatever it is that
17:23 that's fine right I mean at the very beginning of UPB I say come on like what are the odds that
17:29 a software entrepreneur a software entrepreneur turned philosopher has solved the problem of
17:34 secular ethics which has bedeviled philosophy since there was such a thing as philosophy
17:38 what are the odds very low I understand your skepticism so I get all of that but when people
17:44 state the blindingly obvious to me and now there's been a bunch of them but they think that they're
17:48 adding great value I have I have questions okay so then he says the question is why would someone
17:54 want to talk about or even promise bad consequences and so on page seven in then he quotes me he says
18:01 for a truth argument to have value we must value the truth for a value argument to have meaning it
18:06 must be true all right fine with that he says a consequentialist argument about bad consequences
18:12 is made because the arguer believes he has knowledge about why the outcome will be bad
18:17 that's not true and that's not even close to true so hang on we'll get to that in a sec
18:21 seeing this as a threat and therefore invalidating the argument could mean to invalidate the person's
18:26 experience what so instead the empiricist should tackle it by asking for the evidence of the
18:31 experience which is what Stefan does when asking how do you know it's not a rhetorical question
18:36 all right so again we have to break the stand and I can very quickly tell I could very quickly tell
18:42 when someone is not being very critical of their own writing and I gotta tell you for me at least
18:51 somebody who's not critical of his own writing is a problem because they waste other people's time
18:59 right they waste other people's time because if I have to go through and critique your text right
19:07 if I have to go through and critique your text already then you have been somewhat disrespectful
19:14 I think and you have wasted my time it's sort of like if somebody sends me an email that's
19:21 full of spelling errors then I know they haven't carefully read the email to the point where at
19:27 least I don't have to try and puzzle out what they're saying because their words are misspelled
19:31 I get this in live streams though I understand live streams is more of a live typing situation
19:34 but I do ask people to proofread their text before they send them to me to make sure that
19:39 we don't waste everyone's time so he says a consequentialist argument about bad consequences
19:44 is made because the arguer believes he has knowledge about why the outcome will be bad
19:48 that's that's not true that's not true so the first thing is that the arguer of a consequentialist
19:58 argument bad consequences the arguer first claims that he has knowledge about what the outcome will
20:04 be that's what he first has to make the question of whether something is good or bad is subsequent
20:12 to the question of whether the thing will happen or not right so if I were to say to you being
20:18 kidnapped by other dimensional unicorns is a bad thing would we get into that debate right away
20:24 no you would say well hang on I mean being kidnapped by other dimensional unicorns is not
20:30 a thing at all it's not a thing at all now if I said being hit by a meteor is bad we could say
20:35 well yes I mean the odds are very small but you could theoretically be hit by a meteor but if I
20:39 say being mugged by a square circle is bad discuss right the first thing would be well not well is it
20:45 bad or not the first question would be well hang on sorry wait a sec square circles don't exist so
20:50 why are we talking about this thing that that doesn't exist right I hope that that makes sense
20:56 but so the consequentialist is first of all claiming that he knows what the outcome will be
21:01 and then he claims that the outcome will be bad and then he needs to claim that the outcome
21:06 will be bad but still better than all other possible alternatives so first he has to claim
21:12 that he knows what the outcome of a choice will be and the second thing he needs to claim even if he
21:20 wants to stay within the bounds of consequentialism first he has to claim he knows what the outcome
21:23 will be and second he has to claim that he knows for a fact that this is either the very best or
21:28 the least worst of all possible outcomes right so if you get cancer and you you take a chemo the
21:35 outcome will be that you lose your hair but I mean assuming that the chemo is going to save your life
21:40 it's better than the alternative right so there's a lot he says he has knowledge about why the
21:47 outcome will be bad but he doesn't he has to first claim that he knows what the outcome will be
21:52 and then he says seeing this as a threat and therefore invalidating the argument
21:56 could mean to invalidate the person's experience now that's very confusing that's very confusing
22:02 invalidating the person's experience I don't know what that means other than it seems kind of girly
22:09 to put it my tooth I'm sorry there's a bit of a negative statement about girls but what does that
22:15 mean to invalidate a person's experience I've this is sort of a modern thing that happens you know my
22:21 my lived truth or my my personal journey or whatever it is it's like well hey man I don't
22:26 want to invalidate your lived experience unless you're going to make a universal claim of truth
22:31 and objectivity then your lived experience is irrelevant right I mean can you imagine as a kid
22:37 you write two and two makes five and the teacher corrects you and say no no no my lived experience
22:41 is that two and two make five you say that two and two make four but my lived experience is that two
22:45 and two make five my my personal experience my my vivid sense of blah blah blah well I mean that
22:51 doesn't make any sense right my lived experience is that a square circle is possible or whatever it
22:55 is right so invalidating the argument could mean to invalidate the person's experience
23:00 why on earth would I care about invalidating the person's experience the person's experience
23:05 by definition is subjective if it's objective it's the person's argument so invalidating the
23:11 person's experience I don't I don't know I mean that's like basically saying I feel that it's
23:16 true it's like well that's that's an interesting feeling first of all it's not a feeling
23:20 it's a sophisticated quote argument masquerading as emotional manipulation all right so instead
23:26 the empiricist should tackle it by asking for the evidence of the experience which is what
23:31 Steph does when asking how do you know it's not a rhetorical question well when I say how do you know
23:38 I'm not asking for evidence of experience I mean if you had a dream about an elephant last night
23:45 you have that experience I can't get proof of that experience for obvious reasons so when I say how
23:53 do you know you had a dream about an elephant last night you'd say well I very vividly remember it
23:58 and I was riding on its back or this that and the other right so when I ask how do you know
24:03 the question is if somebody says this particular moral argument will have a bad outcome in the
24:10 future I would say well how do you know like you're making a knowledge claim about the outcome
24:16 of a moral argument which means that you know the future and there's a self-detonating statement
24:23 in that right if you know the future it means that there's no free will right physicists know
24:31 what's going to happen to the future right in the future they know how matter and energy are going
24:37 to behave as do engineers because matter and energy don't have free will like a bridge doesn't
24:43 have free will and can't decide to shrug off its itchy burden of back trucks and go scampering off
24:48 to pick grapes in Queensland right so where there's no free will we can accurately predict the future
24:54 whether it's free will we cannot because of free will so the reason that the consequentialist is
25:00 has a self-detonating statement a self-contradiction embedded is he's saying
25:06 I want to change your mind about the future because I know in the future there's no such
25:12 thing as free will I know in the future there's no such thing as free will I know that there's
25:18 no such thing as free will in the future therefore I want to change your mind by appealing to your
25:26 free will in the present which of course makes no sense at all over the course of making the
25:32 argument to change my mind to appeal to my free will in the course of making the argument he's
25:38 moving from the past from the present into the future over the course of making it and he's
25:42 saying free will exists in the future but never in the present which makes no sense at all if
25:47 you're going to change people's minds if you want to change people's minds you have to accept that
25:51 you don't know jack crap about what's happening in the future you just don't I mean you don't
25:57 even know if the person you're debating is going to change his or her mind I mean you hope if
26:02 you make good arguments that they will but you can't guarantee it trust me this one I know right
26:06 it doesn't matter how good an argument you make some people will change their mind some people
26:09 won't you can't predict which is which who is who so the moment you try and change someone's mind
26:16 you have to accept that you don't know what's going to happen in the future because of free
26:21 will because of free will so that's why consequentialism is so I mean honestly it's
26:27 just completely ridiculous so self-contradictory right you can't at the same time say I know for
26:35 certain what everyone's choices are going to be in the future which means that they're not choices
26:39 but people are a species of physics with no free will and I want to change your mind in the present
26:45 if human beings have free will you don't know what's going to happen in the future
26:50 if human beings don't have free will it makes no sense to debate them because you then you
26:56 might as well debate a rock right so then he says consequentialism and bribery he said bribery is
27:01 the offering giving receiving or soliciting of any item of value to influence the actions of a person
27:05 I mean again I what can I really say I mean I and I know what bribery is trust me I've been
27:16 offered bribes in my life I know what bribery is so we are talking about subjectively good
27:21 consequences the question arises can consequences also be objectively good now we are entering the
27:26 domain of the so-called common good concept every rational thinker should be at war with and it's
27:31 true it's the crucial concept hijacked by all political evildoers in the history of the universe
27:35 in other words people are bribed with the promise of a common good all the time other common good
27:39 okay a consequentialist argument about good consequences is made because the arguer believes
27:43 he has knowledge about why the outcome will be good the same logic applies how do you know and
27:48 what kind of good are you talking about at that point UPP can be applied the necessary action for
27:53 the achieving the outcome for achieving the outcome can be considered good as long as there is one
27:58 evidence of either a win-win situation or prevention of an unwanted win-lose situation
28:02 and two a good reason to assume that the outcome is universally consistent so a consequentialist
28:09 argument about good consequences and necessary the necessary action for achieving the outcome
28:14 can be considered good as long as there is one evidence of either a win-win situation or
28:18 prevention of an unwanted win-lose situation and two a good reason to assume that the outcome is
28:23 universally consistent yeah evidence of a good reason to assume these are not philosophical
28:29 arguments philosophical arguments for ethics need to be absolutely ironclad and undisputable
28:34 indisputable indisputable because we're talking about the use of force violence right violence
28:40 takes no prisoners so intellectually morality should take no prisoners right so of course
28:46 violence does take prisoners but you know what i mean right so evidence of either a win-win
28:50 situation or prevention of an unwanted win-lose situation i don't know what any of this means
28:53 so people will say of course well we can't end the welfare state because people will be poorer okay
29:00 i absolutely accept that that that people who are taking money from other people through the power
29:08 of the state if that stops then some people will be poorer i mean in the short run for sure yeah
29:13 absolutely so so what is that i mean here's here's a good question here's a good question for people
29:18 who want to be moralists if your argument can ever be used to justify uh slavery it's a it's like the
29:25 coma test right if your argument can ever be used to justify slavery then he's a bad argument my
29:29 friend he's a bad argument he's no good so if we say well you know some people are affected
29:37 negatively by the end of slavery well sure yeah absolutely slave owners slave catchers all the
29:42 judges who adjudicate slave contracts and disputes and so on right they will be affected negatively
29:48 negatively by the end of slavery so you say ah well but in general it's a good thing it's like
29:54 well the moment you start to say in general you're in the realm of subjectivity you're in the realm
29:58 of subjectivity and some people may do badly materially as the result of a moral change
30:06 but they may also be happier about that so i mean people who are addicted to a particular substance
30:14 if that substance becomes unavailable for some reason either the dealer moves away or they go
30:20 to prison or whatever it is right the substance becomes unavailable they would go through
30:23 withdrawal but they're happy about that so you know that they're relieved that the drug is no
30:29 longer available i mean i'm sure we've all had it if you have a particular food weakness right
30:34 whatever it is that you indulge if it's around so you decide not to buy it not have it in your house
30:40 and then you're kind of snacky and you go to the cupboard and you feel like whatever it is that
30:43 you like to snack on that's bad for you and then you remember oh i didn't buy it it's not here
30:48 and you're like oh thank goodness otherwise i would have eaten it right so a negative consequence
30:53 can be uh welcomed can be welcomed so it we're all talking about subjective stuff we make decisions
31:00 based on principles so consequentialism and principles consequentialists do not necessarily
31:07 stand in the way of principles again it's just a statement no definition and it's funny because
31:11 he's defined bribery but he hasn't defined principle which do you think is more which
31:18 do you think is more important to define bribery or principles all right he says every consequence
31:22 is the result of behavior for a consequentialist it doesn't matter whether a choice is made because
31:27 of principles or out of subjective personal interest consequentialism doesn't prefer the
31:33 one over the other there are consequentialists who prefer a subjective good without any moral
31:37 contemplation and there are consequentialists who act upon principles for what they believe
31:40 would be objectively good so he's just saying constant people who believe in consequentialism
31:46 don't care whether you make a decision out of principles or subjective personal interest
31:52 i mean that seems important if a moral a moral system aims to improve mankind it should promote
31:58 making decisions based on principles it seems to me it seems to me it's sort of like saying well
32:03 your body doesn't care if you cut back on calories because of willpower or because you're locked in a
32:08 basement okay i mean i get that and he says consequentialism doesn't prefer the one over the
32:15 other and okay he's just making statements i still don't know what his definition of principles are
32:21 or our outcomes or how consequentialists magically know the future which is unknowable because of
32:26 free will see everybody with bad arguments wants an external authority to appeal to right the
32:33 appeal to authority is foundational to almost all sophistry and so whether that authority is the
32:38 world health organization or dr fauci or a god or whatever right and and for some people the
32:46 authority is a magical knowledge of the future i mean honestly when people say well we should do
32:52 this because there'll be good outcomes in the future it's the exact epistemological equivalent
32:56 of somebody saying we should do this because my magical elf friend tells me it'll make him happy
33:00 my invisible magical elf friends tells me it will make him happy so you should do this thing
33:05 it's like okay i'm sorry that you have these delusions but that's not an argument so again i'm
33:12 lack of definition and and consequentialism doesn't prefer whether you make decisions based
33:16 on principles or subjective personal interest again you can make these claims but now you're
33:23 saying that all consequentialists are completely indifferent as to whether somebody makes a
33:27 decision based on principles or out of subjective personal interest but consequentialism is a moral
33:32 argument claiming that is a preferred state and that preferred state is better outcomes in the
33:36 future so you can't say that a moralist who claims a universal preferred state is completely
33:42 indifferent as to whether you prefer a universal preferred state or you just happen to like x y or
33:47 z right again a a moral argument is a universally preferred state that people should behave because
33:55 it's better universally and he says universally earlier and then he says well but it doesn't
33:59 matter if you're subjective or not so the moral argument is saying that it doesn't matter whether
34:04 you make a decision based on a moral argument or not well then why am i listening to somebody
34:08 make a moral argument anyway he says in fact everyone is acting upon principles anyway
34:12 that's kind of confusing right doesn't matter whether you act on principles or not but everyone
34:18 acts on principles anyway the principle of pursuing a subjective good disregarding morality
34:22 is called selfishness the principle of pursuing the objective good would be technically be
34:29 unselfishness but that term doesn't quite fit as the objective good encompasses the self as well
34:34 however the question is not whether and unfortunately he he spells whether without
34:39 the h1 whether you act upon principles or not the question is are you honest about the principles
34:43 you align yourself with now this the word principles here is doing a heck of a lot of
34:46 work right this is a a very hard working because principles a principled man generally means that
34:52 he has abstract universal ideals right some moral principles right and now he's saying that
34:57 principles now doesn't mean morality it means justification and the fact that he defines
35:03 bribery but then has contradictory definitions of principles is obviously kind of messy all right
35:08 the question is are you honest about the principles you align yourself with
35:12 so now we have it doesn't matter whether you make a choice because the principles are out of
35:18 subjective personal interest but now the most important question is are you honest about the
35:22 principles you align yourself with so now honesty is a great value so wait a minute if you're a
35:27 consequentialist it doesn't matter whether you have principles or not but it's really important
35:31 that you have the principle called honesty okay sorry it's a mess all right let's do do one or
35:38 two more i find this i find this stuff interesting and i hope it's helpful to you as well the
35:42 pragmatic mind is his note and he quotes from my book the art of the argument atheists also tend
35:50 to prefer consequentialism or outcome-based moral standards that which produces direct and immediate
35:54 benefits in society is considered the good the greatest good for the greatest number and so on
35:58 these are not principled arguments but pragmatic arguments the principled argument against the
36:02 welfare state is that it violates property rights thou shalt not steal the consequentialist argument
36:07 for the welfare state is that it immediately reduces the amount of poverty in society and he
36:12 says stephan is technically correct about it being a consequentialist argument but incorrect in this
36:16 assumption of every consequentialist argument being limited to direct and immediate benefits
36:22 well of course right so if i say that butter contains fat right and if you want to lose
36:29 weight you might want to cut back on your butter not advice just an example right if i say butter
36:35 contains fat and you know fat is a lot of calories and then somebody loftily informs me that there
36:40 are other things in butter besides fat and and by the way steph didn't you know that there are other
36:46 foods that also contain fat i'd be like well yeah isn't this kind of taken for granted so when i
36:52 give an example of a consequentialist argument i'm not saying that every consequentialist argument
36:58 follows this pattern i never made that claim right the principled argument against the welfare state
37:04 is that it violates property rights the consequentialist argument for the welfare state
37:07 is that it immediately reduces the amount of poverty in society but i didn't say that all
37:11 consequentialist arguments follow that pattern so again it's a straw man right he says this as
37:16 far as i'm concerned is because an empiricist tends to be pragmatic yeah the word pragmatic
37:20 is just another one of these words that people use to create vague sounding positive noises
37:26 from their mouth hole without actually making an argument he's not he's defined again he's
37:30 defined the word bribery he defined a bunch of other stuff but he hasn't defined the word
37:35 pragmatic right the empiricist wrestles with reality for evidence so he prefers direct and
37:40 immediate evidence over long-term evidence in the same way a selfish person would prefer direct and
37:44 immediate benefits over long-term benefits the empiricist wrestles with reality for evidence
37:49 what does this mean the empiricist wrestles with reality he hasn't defined reality he hasn't defined
37:55 evidence he hasn't really defined empiricist so i just have to kind of gloss over that right so
38:01 then he says the duality of consequentialism consequentialism can be divided into moral
38:05 consequentialism and amoral consequentialism focusing on direct and immediate benefits
38:09 would be amoral consequentialism because it doesn't care about moral issues i call that
38:14 benefitism because the benefit is considered the highest value while the potential costs are
38:18 overlooked a good example for moral consequentialism is upb itself why is the behavior universally
38:24 preferable because acting upon universals is believed to result in good consequences
38:27 what on earth is that there's nothing to do with anything when have i ever said
38:32 believing acting upon universals is believed to result in good consequences now i do think
38:38 of course that a respect for property rights is going to generate more wealth in society than
38:42 an endless violation of property rights sure and i do talk about the evidence of
38:48 an adherence to universals there is evidence historical evidence because acting upon
38:54 universals is believed to result in good consequences is there any evidence for that
38:58 there certainly is but is the evidence universal the empiricist cannot give a final answer that's
39:03 why stephan provided logical proof through deductive reasoning okay yeah so that's fair
39:06 okay you know what i mean but he says why is the behavior universally preferable because acting on
39:11 universals is believed to result in good consequences consequences so he's saying that my
39:14 that upb has as its preference good consequences you should follow upb because of good consequences
39:21 nope nope nope nope nope nope nope nope not at all not at all and i don't know consequences
39:28 short term or long term the whole reason that we need ethics is because we want to do evil right
39:33 there's a whole reason we need ethics is we want to avoid virtue and do evil like the whole reason
39:37 we need nutrition is because we want to eat things that are bad for us right so because we have
39:41 temptation we need standards to wield against those temptations so upb results in negative
39:47 consequences if you want to steal something and you're like ah upb right so like if you want to
39:53 eat a particular food like you want to eat cheesecake and they say oh we're out of cheesecake
39:57 or we're out of desserts as a whole and you're like oh actually you know it's probably better
40:00 for me like you have a negative consequences you don't get your cheesecake but it's good consequences
40:04 later when you feel better about it so consequences means very little all right so i write he has a
40:10 sit yeah moral consequentialism and amoral consequentialism yeah so can be divided it's
40:15 like yeah i mean okay yeah you can divide things but give me definitions and give me arguments all
40:20 right divine reasoning he wrote deductive reasoning assumes 100 proof assuming all
40:25 premises are correct inescapable perfect divine proof yes divine proof sounds great but how much
40:32 evidence do we have to collect to reach divinity sounds impossible but is that even necessary
40:37 i don't know what to say about that deductive reasoning is 100 proof all men are mortal
40:43 socrates is a man therefore socrates is mortal if all the premises are correct it's 100 certain right
40:48 so this is not evidence to collect to reach divinity this is by definition and then he
40:54 quotes from my book given that premises one and two are valid the conclusion three is inescapable
40:59 what this means is anyone who tries to escape the conclusion is actually trying to escape
41:02 rationality and reality and then he says this is where so many people go into opposition because
41:06 they feel someone is wanting them to not escape regarding the fact that a child generally is not
41:12 allowed to escape its parents in the context of the prevalence of violent parenting that reaction
41:16 shouldn't be surprising i mean to be bullied by lies may lead you to be susceptible to the
41:24 absolutes of truth like feeling bullied quote bullied by truth but i mean what does this mean
41:29 it is a psychological thing and it's interesting that he throws some sort of psychological thing
41:33 into what's supposed to be a moral philosophical and rational argument people don't like reason
41:40 because they were beaten as children okay i mean maybe maybe they don't like absolutes
41:45 because unjust absolutes were inflicted upon them okay yeah i can i can understand that
41:49 i don't know what it has to do with a moral argument about consequentialism but
41:52 all right apophatic inquiry deductive reasoning provides 100 through proof through so-called
42:00 apophasis apophysis the divine proof can't tell us what something is it can only tell us what
42:06 something is not to better understand that concept have a look at mark passio's explanation in the
42:10 second part of his natural law seminar starting at three hours eight minutes and 45 haven't done
42:14 that for example the main premise of upb is that it is universally applicable the main premise of
42:20 upb is that it is universally applicable it's not a premise that's the result of the argument
42:26 in other words you can universally everyone can respect property rights everyone like the respect
42:32 for property rights can be upb the violation of property rights stealing cannot be upb
42:37 because stealing is asymmetrical one person who's the thief wants to take the other person's property
42:42 but it's only stealing if the other person doesn't want the thief to take his property
42:46 so it's asymmetrical the thief wants to take someone else's property violating their property
42:52 rights the other person wants to keep their property maintaining their property right so
42:56 you have an argument for it to be universal that property rights have to be both violated and
43:00 respected which is a contradiction and therefore upb cannot be universalized it's an argument
43:03 so i don't know what the premise of upb is that universally applicable in other words the outcome
43:09 of upb is supposed to result in consistent consequences independent of time space and
43:13 whether the bubble dingles are swollen or not i mean i get he's joking right so it's a logically
43:19 correct consequentialist argument what the outcome of upb is supposed to result in consistent
43:24 consequences independent of time space no i mean the it's i mean it's almost like a tautology if
43:31 you claim that your premise i'm sorry if you claim that your argument is universal then it has to be
43:37 universal it's sort of baked into the definition right if you claim to have an argument about the
43:41 behavior of matter and energy then it's universal right e equals mc squared is universal the inverse
43:47 square law is universal gas is expanded when heated that's universal it's not one place in
43:54 philadelphia and another place in arkansas right a different so if you make a claim that applies
44:01 universally then that claim has to apply universally and if it doesn't then it's not universal right
44:07 all right let's see here but do we have non-divine evidence that it is true well we have thousands of
44:13 years of empirical data indicating that ignoring upb results in harm abuse in slavery chaos you
44:18 name it we know what upb is not and we see its opposite manifesting in the world that's a hell
44:22 of a good start no right yeah so i mean yes of course i think that i think that pursuing virtue
44:28 will often lead to positive outcomes but it leads to negative outcomes for a lot of people who
44:32 profit from evil doing so all right determinism he writes determinism is the philosophical view
44:38 that events are completely determined by previously existing causes there is no atheist that considers
44:42 determinism to be true and for good reason because one could ask what's the first cause then what do
44:48 many atheists consider determinism to be true sam harris i think richard dawkins has stumbled in
44:53 this so and again there are lots of atheists that consider determinism to be true so i don't know
44:57 what that means who would ever be able to prove that what the first cause is so let not look at
45:03 god creating the big bang but instead of reality all right does determinism occur in our everyday
45:07 lives is it observable how many people walk over the edge of a skyscraper and survive how many fly
45:11 away like superman okay so it's human beings are subject to physical laws yes absolutely you cannot
45:17 walk off a skyscraper and not fall right but you have a choice about whether to walk off a
45:22 skyscraper that's where the free will is not the free will to completely surmount reality that would
45:25 be being a god he says we have a lot of experience in falling but not so much experience in levitation
45:31 so we have a good reason to assume that gravity is determined however that is done but does that
45:36 mean that everything is predetermined again there are physical laws yes and there's human beings
45:43 who have free will so predeterminism now predeterminism is the idea that everything is set
45:48 in stone and we have no say in what is happening at all predeterminism denies the existence of
45:52 free will it's based on it's based on the oversimplification of the concept of free will
45:58 stemming from a childish understanding of what freedom is you see just because you can't fly
46:02 like neo in the matrix doesn't mean you are not free yes there's gravity yes it's pulling us down
46:06 every one of us and empirical data so far shows it's working 100 of the time do you know how to
46:11 overcome gravity by willpower alone no well then you are not free of gravity now like everybody
46:16 else does that mean gravity can't be overcome by willpower ever how do you know well i mean
46:22 saying that human beings are subject to physical laws is not any big profound statement now you
46:26 could say of course that you can a will overcoming gravity right you can't fly but you can build a
46:35 plane you can get in a plane you can choose to quote fly because you have chosen to defy gravity
46:42 in a sense right by creating aircraft or hot air balloons or hang gliders or whatever that can
46:48 propel human beings through the air which human beings can't do on their own so choosing like i
46:53 can't choose to go for an hour walk in the bitter cold without you know risking death unless i choose
46:59 to put on bulky warm heavy clothing and so on right i can't choose to slide down a snowy hill
47:06 unless i put skis on right so i mean choices can not i mean they obviously airplanes use gravity
47:15 and wind resistance and someone for their propulsion and elevation but human beings can't
47:21 fly but we can quote defy gravity by making the choices to build things that allow us to do what
47:26 we couldn't do on our own so yeah gravity can't be overcome by willpower ever how do you know
47:32 so what he's saying is that there should be grave doubt or there could be legitimate doubt about
47:41 the universality and existence of gravity right but so so that which we have experienced
47:48 100 we see everywhere all the time and there's no exceptions and there are scientific
47:54 conjectures hypothesis theories and proofs that gravity is 100 so if we can't be certain of
48:02 gravity then we can't be certain of anything right so he's saying that consequentialism is good
48:08 because people can know the future they can know the outcomes of complex socio-economic decisions
48:15 like the welfare state or whatever right so he's saying that consequentialism has value because
48:20 we can know the future but you can't know gravity i mean you see what i'm saying we can't know that
48:26 which is objectively empirically universally true and proven by every facet and evidence of
48:30 our experience in science and theory and reality and atoms and right so a foundational aspect of
48:36 the universe that is 100 validated by experience and theory well we can't be certain of that but
48:42 boy we can be certain about the outcomes of complex socio-economic decisions that made by
48:47 the state right so i don't quite i mean if we can't be certain of gravity let's say that we
48:51 can't we can't be certain of anything then there's no such thing as consequentialism because if we
48:54 can't be certain of reason evidence and everything we've ever experienced and everything that science
48:59 validates if we can't be certain of that then of course we can't possibly be certain of anything
49:04 that happens in the future and therefore consequentialism is invalid all right uh he
49:10 says let's oh then he quotes from my book one of the reasons why clear definitions at the beginning
49:14 at the beginning of a debate are so important is that they help you avoid wasting time in
49:18 synonym logic i agree with that it's from page 13 of art of the argument heart of the argument.com
49:24 he says let's be clear about that predeterminism is not the same as determinism
49:29 predeterminism is a foolish concept leading to the destructive mindset of a nihilist
49:34 okay predeterminism is the idea that everything is set in stone and we have no say in what is
49:39 happening at all he says it's a foolish concept why i mean saying that something is a foolish
49:44 concept is not an argument leading to the destructive mindset of a nihilist okay let's
49:50 say it does that's a consequentialist argument right that's like saying you shouldn't die because
49:55 you'll be unhappy a determinism he says on the other hand doesn't touch the future as it causes
50:00 as causes by definition will exist as long as there is time what determinism on the other hand
50:06 doesn't touch the future as causes by definition will exist as long as there is time so who causes
50:12 causes can you cause something to happen you see it doesn't matter who began it's like trying to
50:17 make the case that a thunderstorm in 10 000 bc caused water damage in your apartment in 2023
50:21 that's what you do if you want to win the nobel prize prize in nitpicking i don't i don't understand
50:28 sorry i don't i don't understand anything about this determinism on the other hand doesn't touch
50:33 the future oh is this that idea that you don't know what's coming next in a movie but you know
50:40 that it's prescriptive i've heard that argument before compatibilism i think it's called it still
50:46 doesn't make any sense all right i mean i don't argue with a movie if i'm arguing with a person
50:49 right you know you hear these people in movie theaters uh when there's a horror movie saying
50:54 don't do that don't run don't go down that hope you know that the movie's already done right you
50:58 know i mean it's kind of a foolish thing it's kind of a goofy foolish thing to do to argue with a
51:02 character in a movie where the movie's already been shot and it's fixed in stone right so
51:06 consequentialism sorry compatibilism doesn't make any more sense so what actually matters is what is
51:11 happening here and now and what we choose to do to better understand how determinism and free will
51:16 coexist have a look at mark pastries explanation of the mental schism and the worldview schism at
51:20 the beginning of the second part of the natural law seminar yeah i mean i i kind of get where
51:25 you're coming from but if you're going to make an argument like if you're competent to make the
51:30 argument then make the argument if you're saying this guy has a great argument then you're not good
51:35 at explaining it and so if you're not good at explaining the argument then i won't particularly
51:41 care what you have to say right if you're saying well mark mark passio or whatever he makes the
51:47 really good argument well if you can't summarize it for me then you don't understand it well enough
51:53 to explain it to someone else right just a big test of whether you understand something is can
51:56 you explain it particularly in fairly simple terms to someone else i mean i think it was einstein who
52:01 boiled down the theory of relativity or someone did boil down the theory of relativity into like
52:05 less than 300 words for a telegram and it was it was masterly right or the old quote from
52:10 wisden churchill i'm sorry that i i'm sorry this is such a long letter i didn't have time to write
52:14 a shorter one right so can you can you make the argument now he hasn't actually defined
52:21 what determinism is he just says it doesn't touch the future as causes by definition will exist as
52:28 long as there is time so he he literally quotes me in saying one of the reasons why clear definitions
52:34 at the beginning of a debate is so important is that they help you avoid wasting time on synonym
52:38 logic and he but he doesn't define determinism and how it's differentiated from predeterminism so
52:46 that's somebody who's not alive in thought in the moment right so if i say clear definitions
52:52 are important and he's trying to explain to me the difference between predeterminism and
52:58 determinism and he hasn't defined the differentiation differentiation between the terms then he's not
53:04 thinking in the moment this is all i don't know some sort of emotional defense usually these are
53:07 people who've done bad things in their life and they take refuge in determinism so they don't
53:10 have to confront their own conscience which doesn't work but it's strangely compelling for a lot of
53:14 people so yeah i hope this helps i really do appreciate people sending me this stuff in i do
53:19 find it very interesting and valuable to go through freedom.com/donate bye everyone talk to you soon